Hi Music lovers, here you can download a list of International Music and Music of Indonesia, may be useful and to LIVE YOUR MUSIC
Definition of music
How to define music has long been the subject of debate; philosophers, musicians, and, more recently, various social and natural scientists have argued about what constitutes music. The definition has varied through history, in different regions, and within societies. Definitions vary as music, like art, is a subjectively perceived phenomenon. Its definition has been tackled by philosophers of art, lexicographers, composers, music critics, musicians, semioticians or semiologists, linguists, sociologists, and neurologists. Music may be defined according to various criteria including organization, pleasantness, intent, social construction, perceptual processes and engagement, universal aspects or family resemblances, and through contrast or negative definition.
Etymology
The word music comes from the Greek mousikê (tekhnê) by way of the Latin musica. It is ultimately derived from mousa, the Greek word for muse. In ancient Greece, the word mousike was used to mean any of the arts or sciences governed by the Muses. Later, in Rome, ars musica embraced poetry as well as instrument-oriented music. In the European Middle Ages, musica was part of the mathematical quadrivium: arithmetics, geometry, astronomy and musica. The concept of musica was split into four major kinds by the fifth century philosopher, Boethius: musica universalis, musica humana, musica instrumentalis, and musica divina. Of those, only musica instrumentalis referred to music as performed sound.
Musica universalis or musica mundana referred to the order of the universe, as God had created it in "measure, number and weight". The proportions of the spheres
of the planets and stars (which at the time were still thought to
revolve around the earth) were perceived as a form of music, without
necessarily implying that any sound would be heard—music
refers strictly to the mathematical proportions. From this concept
later resulted the romantic idea of a music of the spheres. Musica
humana, designated the proportions of the human body.
These were thought to reflect the proportions of the Heavens and as
such, to be an expression of God's greatness. To Medieval thinking, all
things were connected with each other—a mode of thought that finds its
traces today in the occult sciences or esoteric thought—ranging from astrology to believing certain minerals have certain beneficiary effects.
Musica instrumentalis, finally, was the lowliest of the three
disciplines and referred to the manifestation of those same mathematical
proportions in sound—be it sung or played on instruments. The
polyphonic organization of different melodies to sound at the same time
was still a relatively new invention then, and it is understandable that
the mathematical or physical relationships in frequency that give rise to the musical intervals as we hear them, should be foremost among the preoccupations of Medieval musicians.
Translations
The languages of many cultures do not include a word for or that would be translated as music. Inuit and most North American Indian languages do not have a general term for music. Among the Aztecs, the ancient Mexican theory of rhetorics, poetry, dance, and instrumental music, used the Nahuatl term In xochitl-in kwikatl to refer a complex mix of music and other poetic verbal and non-verbal elements, and reserve the word Kwikakayotl (or cuicacayotl) only for the sung expressions (Leon-Portilla 2007, 11). In Africa there is no term for music in Tiv, Yoruba, Igbo, Efik, Birom, Hausa, Idoma, Eggon or Jarawa. Many other languages have terms which only partly cover what Europeans mean by the term music (Schafer). The Mapuche of Argentina do not have a word for music, but they do have words for instrumental versus improvised forms (kantun), European and non-Mapuche music (kantun winka), ceremonial songs (öl), and tayil (Robertson 1976, 39).
Some languages in West Africa have no term for music but the speakers do have the concept (Nettl 1989,[page needed]). Musiqi is the Persian word for the science and art of music, muzik being the sound and performance of music (Sakata 1983,[page needed]), though some things European influenced listeners would include, such as Quran chanting, are excluded. Actually, there are varying degrees of "musicness"; Quran chanting and Adhan is not considered music, but classical improvised song, classical instrumental metric composition, and popular dance music are.
However, most Indian languages have specific words that mean music or in some way denote it, for example 'Sangeeth' in Hindi and 'Sangeetham' in Malayalam both mean music.
Definitions
Organized sound
An often-cited definition of music, coined by Edgard Varèse, is that it is "organized sound" (Goldman 1961, 133). The fifteenth edition of the Encyclopædia Britannica
describes that "while there are no sounds that can be described as
inherently unmusical, musicians in each culture have tended to restrict
the range of sounds they will admit."
"Organization" also seems necessary because it implies purposeful and thus human organization.[citation needed]
This human organizing element seems crucial to the common understanding
of music. Sounds produced by non-human agents, such as waterfalls or
birds, are often described as "musical", but rarely as "music". See zoomusicology.
Additionally, Schaeffer (1968, 284) describes that the sound of
classical music "has decays; it is granular; it has attacks; it
fluctuates, swollen with impurities—and all this creates a musicality
that comes before any 'cultural' musicality." Yet the definition
according to the esthesic level does not allow that the sounds of
classical music are complex, are noises, rather they are regular,
periodic, even, musical sounds. Nattiez (1990, 47—48): "My own position
can be summarized in the following terms: just as music is whatever people choose to recognize as such, noise is whatever is recognized as disturbing, unpleasant, or both." (see "music as social construct" below)
Language
Main article: Musical language
Many definitions of music implicitly hold that music is a
communicative activity which conveys to the listener moods, emotions,
thoughts, impressions, or philosophical, sexual, or political concepts
or positions. "Musical language" may be used to mean style or genre,
while music may be treated as language without being called such, as in
Fred Lerdahl or others' analysis of musical grammar. Levi R. Bryant defines music not as a language, but as a marked-based, problem-solving method such as mathematics (Ashby 2004, 4).
Subjective experience
Main article: Aesthetics of music
This view of music is most heavily criticized by proponents of the
view that music is a social construction (directly below), defined in
opposition to "unpleasant" "noise", though this view may be subsumed in
the one below in that a listener's idea of pleasant sounds may be
considered socially constructed. A subjective definition of music need
not, however, be limited to traditional ideas of music as pleasant or
melodious. This approach to the definition focuses not on the construction but on the experience
of music. Thus, music could include "found" sound structures—produced
by natural phenomena or algorithms—as long as they are interpreted by
means of the aesthetic cognitive processes involved in music
appreciation. This approach permits the boundary between music and noise
to change over time as the conventions of musical interpretation evolve
within a culture, to be different in different cultures at any given
moment, and to vary from person to person according to their experience
and proclivities. It is further consistent with the subjective reality
that even what would commonly be considered music is experienced as
nonmusic if the mind is concentrating on other matters and thus not
perceiving the sound's essence as music (Clifton 1983, 9).
Social construct
Main article: Ethnomusicology
Post-modern and other theories argue that, like all art, music is defined primarily by social context. According to this view, music is what people call music, whether it is a period of silence, found sounds, or performance.
Cage, Kagel, Schnebel, and others, according to Nattiez (1987, 43),
"perceive [certain of their pieces] (even if they do not say so
publicly) as a way of "speaking" in music about music, in the second
degree, as it were, to expose or denounce the institutional aspect of
music's functioning."Cultural background is a factor in determining
music from noise or unpleasant experiences. The experience of only being
exposed to a particular type of music influences perception of any
music. Cultures of European descent are largely influenced by music
making use of the Diatonic scale.
It might be added that as well as cultural background, historical era
is also a determining factor in what is regarded as music. What would
today be accepted as music in the west without the blinking of an eye,
would have been ridiculed in the 17th century.[citation needed]
Many people do, however, share a general idea of music. The Websters
definition of music is a typical example: "the science or art of
ordering tones or sounds in succession, in combination, and in temporal
relationships to produce a composition having unity and continuity" (Webster's Collegiate Dictionary, online edition). There are a number of potential objections to such a definition.[vague]
The composer John Cage challenged traditional ideas about music in his 4' 33", which is notated as three movements, each marked Tacet (that is, "do not play").
Musical universals
Main article: Aspect of music
Often a definition of music lists the aspects or elements that make
up music under that definition. However, in addition to a lack of
consensus, Jean Molino
(1975, 43) also points out that "any element belonging to the total
musical fact can be isolated, or taken as a strategic variable of
musical production." Nattiez gives as examples Mauricio Kagel's Con Voce [with voice], where a masked trio silently mimes playing instruments.
Following Wittgenstein, cognitive psychologist Eleanor Rosch
proposes that categories are not clean cut but that something may be
more or less a member of a category (Rosch 1973, 328). As such the
search for musical universals would fail and would not provide one with a
valid definition (Levitin 2006, 136–39).
Specific definitions
Clifton
In his 1983 book, Music as Heard, which sets out from the phenomenological position of Husserl, Merleau-Ponty, and Ricœur, Thomas Clifton defines music as "an ordered arrangement of sounds and silences whose meaning is presentative rather than denotative.
. . . This definition distinguishes music, as an end in itself, from
compositional technique, and from sounds as purely physical objects."
More precisely, "music is the actualization of the possibility of any
sound whatever to present to some human being a meaning which he
experiences with his body—that is to say, with his mind, his feelings,
his senses, his will, and his metabolism" (Clifton 1983, 1). It is
therefore "a certain reciprocal relation established between a person,
his behavior, and a sounding object" (Clifton 1983, 10).
Clifton accordingly differentiates music from nonmusic on the basis
of the human behavior involved, rather than on either the nature of
compositional technique or of sounds as purely physical objects.
Consequently, the distinction becomes a question of what is meant by
musical behavior: "a musically behaving person is one whose very being
is absorbed in the significance of the sounds being experienced."
However, "It is not altogether accurate to say that this person is
listening to the sounds. First, the person is doing more than
listening: he is perceiving, interpreting, judging, and feeling. Second,
the preposition 'to' puts too much stress on the sounds as such. Thus,
the musically behaving person experiences musical significance by means
of, or through, the sounds" (Clifton 1983, 2).
In this framework, Clifton finds that there are two things that
separate music from nonmusic: (1) musical meaning is presentative, and
(2) music and nonmusic are distinguished in the idea of personal
involvement. "It is the notion of personal involvement which lends
significance to the word ordered in this definition of music" (Clifton 1983, 3–4). This is not to be understood, however, as a sanctification of extreme relativism,
since "it is precisely the 'subjective' aspect of experience which
lured many writers earlier in this century down the path of sheer
opinion-mongering. Later on this trend was reversed by a renewed
interest in 'objective,' scientific, or otherwise nonintrospective
musical analysis. But we have good reason to believe that a musical
experience is not a purely private thing, like seeing pink elephants, and that reporting about such an experience need not be subjective in the sense of it being a mere matter of opinion" (Clifton 1983, 8–9).
Clifton's task, then, is to describe musical experience and the
objects of this experience which, together, are called "phenomena," and
the activity of describing phenomena is called "phenomenology" (Clifton
1983, 9). It is important to stress that this definition of music says
nothing about aesthetic standards.
Music is not a fact or a thing in the world, but a meaning constituted by human beings. . . . To talk about such experience in a meaningful way demands several things. First, we have to be willing to let the composition speak to us, to let it reveal its own order and significance. . . . Second, we have to be willing to question our assumptions about the nature and role of musical materials. . . . Last, and perhaps most important, we have to be ready to admit that describing a meaningful experience is itself meaningful. (Clifton 1983, 5–6)
Nattiez
"Music, often an art/entertainment, is a total social fact whose definitions vary according to era and culture," according to Jean Molino (1975, 37). It is often contrasted with noise. According to musicologist Jean-Jacques Nattiez:
"The border between music and noise is always culturally defined—which
implies that, even within a single society, this border does not always
pass through the same place; in short, there is rarely a consensus....
By all accounts there is no single and intercultural
universal concept defining what music might be" (Nattiez 1990, 47–8 and
55). Given the above demonstration that "there is no limit to the number
or the genre of variables that might intervene in a definition of the
musical," (Molino, 1987, 42)[citation needed] an organization of definitions and elements is necessary.
Nattiez (1990, 17; see sign (semiotics)) describes definitions according to a tripartite semiological scheme similar to the following:
Poietic Process | Esthesic Process | |||
Composer (Producer) | → | Sound (Trace) | ← | Listener (Receiver) |
There are three levels of description, the poietic, the neutral, and the esthesic:
- " By 'poietic' I understand describing the link among the composer's intentions, his creative procedures, his mental schemas, and the result of this collection of strategies; that is, the components that go into the work's material embodiment. Poietic description thus also deals with a quite special form of hearing (Varese called it 'the interior ear'): what the composer hears while imagining the work's sonorous results, or while experimenting at the piano, or with tape."
- "By 'esthesic' I understand not merely the artificially attentive hearing of a musicologist, but the description of perceptive behaviors within a given population of listeners; that is how this or that aspect of sonorous reality is captured by their perceptive strategies." (Nattiez 1990, 90)
- The neutral level is that of the physical "trace", (Saussere's sound-image, a sonority, a score), created and interpreted by the esthesic level (which corresponds to a perceptive definition; the perceptive and/or "social" construction definitions below) and the poietic level (which corresponds to a creative, as in compositional, definition; the organizational and social construction definitions below).
Table describing types of definitions of music (Nattiez 1990, 46):
poietic level (choice of the composer) |
neutral level (physical definition) |
esthesic level (perceptive judgment) |
|
music | musical sound | sound of the harmonic spectrum |
agreeable sound |
non music | noise (nonmusical) |
noise (complex sound) |
disagreeable noise |
Because of this range of definitions, the study of music comes in a wide variety of forms. There is the study of sound and vibration or acoustics, the cognitive study of music, the study of music theory and performance practice or music theory and ethnomusicology and the study of the reception and history of music, generally called musicology.
Xenakis
Composer Iannis Xenakis in "Towards a Metamusic" (chapter 7 of Xenakis 1971) defined music in the following way:
- It is a sort of comportment necessary for whoever thinks it and makes it.
- It is an individual pleroma, a realization.
- It is a fixing in sound of imagined virtualities (cosmological, philosophical, . . ., arguments)
- It is normative, that is, unconsciously it is a model for being or for doing by sympathetic drive.
- It is catalytic: its mere presence permits internal psychic or mental transformations in the same way as the crystal ball of the hypnotist.
- It is the gratuitous play of a child.
- It is a mystical (but atheistic) asceticism. Consequently expressions of sadness, joy, love and dramatic situations are only very limited particular instances.
(Xenakis 1971, 181)
Enjoying
Tidak ada komentar:
Posting Komentar